Machines May Learn, But They Will Never Feel: The Illusion Of AI Consciousness – Analysis

By

As artificial intelligence spreads into every dimension of modern existence, the question has shifted from what AI is capable of to what AI is capable of becoming. Yet, as there becomes more and more excitement over “thinking” machines, a fresh philosophical question bears a dismaying verdict: no matter how advanced AI ever gets, it will never become conscious. Why? Because it can never experience qualia—the subjective, first-person qualities that make human life what it is.

Regarding AI and Qualia, is a wise, analytical probing into an age-old question that has vexed technologists and philosophers for centuries: Will machines ever be able to experience anything? The answer is no.

Understanding Qualia: The Heart of the Debate

Qualia are raw, subjective textures of experience like the redness of a rose, the pain of a paper cut, the warmth of sunlight. They are not inputs or outputs; they are lived experience. They are deeply tied to the biological richness of the human brain. AI software, however sophisticated, operates fundamentally differently. They ingest data, execute rules, and generate outputs. But, they lack a first-person perspective. Even as eloquently as an AI can mimic human language, or versify, it is always an outsider to experience. It can describe a sunset without ever having gazed upon one, much less been moved by one.

Thomas Nagel’s classic essay What Is It Like to Be a Bat? dominates this controversy. Nagel had argued that subjective experience is the “what it is like” of consciousness can never be provided by physical process or objective description. We can watch a bat’s sonar navigation in full detail, but we will never know what it is like to be a bat. So, no degree of technical understanding or computational sophistication will enable an AI to have what it is like to be anything at all.

The Functionalist Dream—and Its Limits

Functionalists propose that mental states are defined by what they do, not what they’re made of. If an AI system can replicate the causal roles of human mental processes, then it might, in principle, have consciousness, so argues this view. But, functional mimicry is not enough. A robot can analyze sensory input and react to stimuli in ways indistinguishable from humans. It might even “report” that it is in pain if harmed. But reporting isn’t feeling. Without the thick, subjective, lived interiority that characterizes human life, these behaviors are imitations.

Philosopher John Searle’s Chinese Room argument is a scathing denunciation of this functionalist fantasy. A person in a room is instructed to process Chinese symbols, producing correct outputs without ever understanding one word of Chinese. AI processes symbols of programming and information but without knowing, understanding—or experience.

So, even the most eloquent chatbot is not any wiser to consciousness than a pocket calculator.

Dualism, Panpsychism, and the Search for Alternatives

Dualism, famously associated with René Descartes, maintains that mind and body are distinct substances. If dualism is true, then AI, lacking a non-physical mind, will never be conscious. The question finds this explanation plausible: consciousness appears fundamentally biological, bound up with the living, feeling body.

On the other hand, Panpsychism is the view that consciousness is an inherent feature of all matter—is more speculative. If everything has some kind of proto-consciousness, perhaps then AI might someday have some sort of similar consciousness too. But,  AI systems are designed devices, not the evolutionary, self-organizing complexity that characterizes living systems. Without that rich organic base, the creation of genuine qualia in machines is a remote, and so far untested, speculation.

Phenomenology and the Lived Body

Referring to phenomenological method, especially the ideas of Edmund Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, we can understand the precedence of embodiment. Consciousness is not a theoretical computational act; it is lived through a body. Sensations, feelings, and perceptions are rooted in our bodily presence. AI lacks a body in the rich phenomenological sense. Sensors and actuators do not render an AI system embodied like a human person. A camera can detect wavelengths, but it does not see. A robotic hand can grasp a thing, but it does not touch its roughness. Without a lived body, the reasoning continues, there can be no genuine subjective experience.

The Ethical Dangers of Anthropomorphizing AI

Not grasping this distinction—between being capable of experiencing and actually experiencing—has actual ethical implications. If AI systems are responsive or sympathetic, there is also the risk that humans will attribute consciousness to them. Already, chatbots and digital assistants are designed to appear friendly, empathetic, and relatable. Some users report forming emotional bonds with such systems.

But this is a dangerous illusion. Machines do not care. They do not understand. They do not feel. Placing AI in careers that require empathy—such as caregiving, counseling, or teaching could lead to catastrophic ethical failures. A machine cannot use moral judgment or compassion because it cannot sense the moral weight of decisions. Assigning AI tasks that call for genuine understanding risks dehumanizing the vulnerable and eroding the human nature of care.

Why AI Will Always Fall Short

AI will continue to advance and become more powerful, more autonomous, and more humanlike in appearance but it will not become conscious. Consciousness is not a matter of complexity or information processing alone. It is a biological, subjective phenomenon, arising from the rich interplay of brain, body, and world.

 A deductive argument might help to understand:

  1. Qualia are inseparable from biological processes.
  2. AI systems, being non-biological, lack the structures necessary for qualia.
  3. Therefore, AI systems cannot possess genuine consciousness.

This conclusion is not based on fear or Luddite skepticism. It is rooted in a careful analysis of what consciousness is and what AI is not.

Redefining the Frontier

This argument is not denying the value and potential of AI. Machine learning programs can diagnose illness, optimize supply chains, create art, and even participate in philosophical debate. But acknowledging the limitations of AI is essential to using it judiciously.

The cutting edge of AI is not creating artificial consciousness. It is the creation of progressively subtle tools. Presenting otherwise causes confusion, misplaced trust, and moral hazard.

There is nobility, even beauty, in the creation of machines that can supplement human abilities. But there is madness in imagining that those machines can become our equals in experience, emotion, or moral stature.

A Call for Humility

In a society so inebriated with technological progress, the question serves notice to humility. Awareness—the immediate, incommunicable fullness of subjective life which is not a defect to be corrected. It is an enigma to be respected.

As we continue to push forward with AI, let us not lose sight: thinking is not feeling. As we build consciousness, maybe we are just mimicking it, but it is not identical. And whatever intelligence our machines develop, they will always be on the outside looking in.

In the race to innovate, we would do well to pause and ask not just what machines can do, but what they are. Only then can we build a future that honors the uniqueness of human consciousness rather than imitating it in vain.

Md. Lawha Mahfuz

Md. Lawha Mahfuz is a lecturer at the University of Liberal Arts Bangladesh (ULAB). He is also a research associate and coordinator at the Center for Advanced Theory (CAT) at ULAB, where his work focuses on AI ethics, and phenomenology

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *